How is
gratuitous evil compatible with a loving, good God? When we read of
heartrending tragedies like the recent random knife attack in Taipei, Taiwan,
where a 4-year-old toddler was beheaded in full view of her mother, we can only
lament that this is evil, an act of an evil man. It is truly horrendous evil.
Michael
Peterson writes, “Something is dreadfully wrong with our world. An earthquake
kills hundreds in Peru. A pancreatic cancer patient suffers prolonged,
excruciating pain and dies. A pit bull attacks a two-year-old child, angrily
ripping his flesh and killing him. Countless multitudes suffer the ravages of
war in Somalia. A crazed cult leader pushes eighty-five people to their deaths
in Waco, Texas. Millions starve and die in North Korea as famine ravages the
land. Horrible things of all kinds happen in our world—and that has been the
story since the dawn of civilization.”(Peterson, Michael L. 1998. God and Evil: An Introduction to the Issues.
Boulder, CO: Westview Press.p1).
Admittedly,
the problem of evil is a multifaceted, complex issue. Even if we are finally
able to climb the Mount Everest of the intellectual problem of evil, the personal
problem of evil often challenges even the toughest, hidebound Christian
soldier. When the problem of evil gets personal, it can emaciate the strongest of
faith, and confuse the most logical of minds. And this personal problem of evil
requires pastoral counselling and advice, not philosophical circumlocution and
arguments.
In the
following paragraphs, we are going to have a brief overview of the intellectual
problem of evil, and thereafter, we would focus upon the problem of gratuitous
evil. As for now, we would leave the personal problem aside for a while.
The problem
of evil can broadly be divided into two philosophical problems – the logical or
deductive problem of evil, and the evidential or inductive problem of evil (for
example, the issue of gratuitous evil).
Popularly
formulated by J. L. Mackie in the 1950s, the logical-deductive problem of evil
emerges from four core propositions (Warburton, Nigel. 2004. Philosophy: The Basics (4 ed.).
Routledge. p22):
1. An
all-powerful (omnipotent) God could prevent evil from existing in the world.
2. An
all-knowing (omniscient) God would know that there was evil in the world.
3. An
all-good (omnibenevolent) God would wish to prevent evil from existing in the
world.
4. There is
evil in the world.
Atheologians
insinuate that these core propositions would result in a logical contradiction,
thereby rendering the non-existence of God a necessary truth. In the realm of
philosophy, Christian philosopher Alvin Plantinga seems to have conclusively
rebutted the logical problem of evil (see Plantinga, Alvin (1977). God, Freedom, and Evil. Grand Rapids,
MI: Eerdmans). It is no longer a serious matter of disagreement amongst
philosophers of religion. But from a theological perspective, his rebuttal
still leaves a lot to be desired. From a Reformed, compatibilist understanding,
Plantinga’s free will defence cannot be reconciled with a Christian
anthropology which describes fallen man as having a will inclined towards sin
and evil (i.e. total depravity). Plantinga’s defence presupposes libertarian,
incompatibilist free will, which Reformed thinkers would reject.
An
introduction to gratuitous evil from a Reformed perspective
The problem
of gratuitous evil is not the same as the logical problem of evil. The logical
problem threatens the Theist with the non-existence of God as a necessary
truth. If the logical-deductive problem of evil succeeds, then Christianity is
necessarily false i.e. it is false in all possible worlds.
The problem
of gratuitous evil belongs to the evidential or inductive problem of evil, and
it is at the center of ongoing philosophical debates. If the inductive problem
succeeds, then it is highly probable that God does not exist. Although it is
not a logical contradiction, it does make theistic beliefs less probable and/or
irrational.
The philosophical
problem of gratuitous (or pointless) evil can be formulated as such.
(1)
Gratuitous evils occur.
(2) If God
exists then no gratuitous evils occur.
Therefore,
(3) God does
not exist.
The
inference from (1) and (2) to the conclusion (3) is a valid argument.
Therefore, the soundness of the argument is dependent upon the truthfulness of
the premises. While (1) is the evidential premise, (2) is the theological
premise. Premise (2) is supposed to follow from God’s omnibenevolence. A
perfectly good God wouldn’t permit evil without sufficient justifying reasons,
and hence gratuitous (or pointless) evil shouldn’t occur.
Quite
recently, Alan Rhoda gives us a thoughtful definition of gratuitous evil:
“A
gratuitous evil = A token or type of evil which God antecedently knew he could
have prevented in a way that would have made the world overall better.
In the light
of [the above definition], the theological premise becomes
(2*) If God
exists then there occur no tokens or types of evil which God antecedently knew
he could have prevented in a way that would have made the world overall better.”
(see Alan R. Rhoda. “Gratuitous evil and divine providence.” Religious Studies, Volume 46, Issue 03. September
2010, pp 281-302).
In his paper, Rhoda discusses the various existing definitions
of gratuitous evil, and finally conclude that the aforementioned definition is
one that should be acceptable to all for the purpose of ongoing philosophical
dialogue.
Evidently, Reformed
theists are theological determinists, and as such, “affirms that God is the
ultimate sufficient cause of all events and that God exercises meticulous
providence in virtue of his strongly actualizing a particular possible world,
one which includes a unique and complete history.” (Rhoda, 2010).
Put simply,
“theological determinism is the view that God determines every event that
occurs in the history of the world. … Contemporary theological determinists
also appeal to various biblical texts (for example Ephesians 1:11) and
confessional creeds (for example the Westminster Confession of Faith) to
support their view.” (see http://www.iep.utm.edu/theo-det/)
Rhoda
correctly observes that theological determinists must resist the evidential
premise (1) in his defence. For “theological determinists don’t believe God
actualizes evils for their own sakes, but rather for the sake of goods to which
those evils contribute.” (Rhoda, 2010) Given the perfect goodness of God,
gratuitous evil should not exist. He further comments, “Given their limited
options for theodicy, we might expect theological determinists to rely heavily
on the sceptical response to the evidential argument.” (Rhoda, 2010).
If God is
necessarily good (for example, see Charnock, Stephen. The Existence and Attributes of God. Sovereign Grace Publishers.
Lafayette, IN. p548), then the theological premise (2) must be accepted, for a
perfectly good God wouldn’t allow pointless evil. It follows that, for a
successful theodicy, the evidential premise (1) ought to be rejected or denied
by Reformed thinkers. Alternatively, a defeater can be offered for the
evidential premise.
Richard
Swinburne, in his “Greater Good” theodicy, categorically rejects the concept of
gratuitous evil (the evidential premise). He believes that, for God to allow
this much evil, He will bring about a greater good whether in this life or the
next (see Swinburne, Richard. 1998. Providence
and the Problem of Evil. Oxford: Clarendon Press). He discussed
possibilities for the allowance of evil, including “the good of being used” and
“evil as a teaching aid.” (Swinburne, 1998, p44).
“The good of
being used” relates to the possibility that God permits evil for a person so
that another might benefit from or be spared of the evil. As for evil as a
teaching aid, Swinburne believes that God desires Man to learn the making of
morally good choices, and that “the evils of the kind and quantity we find
around us are required if humans are to have the power to choose between doing
good or evil of varied significant kinds to their fellows.” Swinburne, Richard.
“Some Major Strands of Theodicy,” in The
Evidential Argument From Evil, ed. Daniel Howard-Snyder. Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University Press. 1996, p32.)
The central
weakness of Swinburne’s theodicy is his reliance on the unproven concept of
libertarian free will, which Reformed thinkers reject. But libertarian free
will, according to reformed theology, occurs in the Pre Fall state of Man (posse
peccare, posse non peccare). And it is only after the Fall that Man’s will is
in bondage to his sinful nature (non posse non peccare). Perhaps the Reformed
understanding of anthropology, particularly the state of Man before and after
the Fall, would help us develop a theodicy which is compatible with the
compatibilist view of Fallen Man, while at the same time, takes into account
the libertarian free will Man has prior to the Fall.
“Free-Fall”
theodicies usually state that Divine Goodness would never deliberately or
directly introduce evil into the world. Indeed, God’s creation was very good
prior to the Fall. Augustine believes that sin and its resultant evil and
consequences are not necessary for the perfection of the created universe. But
for God to create the best-of-all-possible-worlds, free creatures (including humans
and angelic beings) are of necessity an integral part of the Divine
perfectness. Hence, these free agents are responsible for the evil that their
creaturely freedom allows, and are directly responsible for the evil that
ensues. God does not intend evil, but rather allows it through His free
creatures.
A
Defeater for Gratuitous Evil
In the
ongoing discussion about gratuitous evil, Marilyn McCord Adams – an
Episcopalian – brings into the debate a breath of fresh air. She defines
gratuitous or horrendous evil as “evils the participation in (the doing or
suffering of) which gives one reason prima facie to doubt whether one’s life
could (given their inclusion in it) be a great good to one on the whole.”
(Adams, Marilyn McCord and
Adams, Robert Merrihew eds. The Problem
of Evil. Oxford University Press. 1990, p211). Or rather, more explicitly:
an evil E is horrendous or gratuitous if and only if participation in E by
person P gives everyone prima facie reason to doubt whether P’s life can, given
P’s participation in E, be a great good to P on the whole.
She aptly
observes that “the debate was carried on at too high a level of abstraction.” (Adams,
Marilyn McCord. Horrendous Evils and the
Goodness of God. Cornell University Press. 2000, p3). She continues to
lament that, while proponents from both sides of the issue persist to adhere to
William Rowe’s understanding of “restricted standard theism,” the important
uniqueness and distinctive doctrines peculiar to historic Christianity have
been ignored.
She
continues, “It does the atheologian no good to argue for the falsity of
Christianity on the ground that the existence of an omnipotent, omniscient,
pleasure-maximizer is incompossible with a world such as ours, because
Christians never believed God was a pleasure-maximizer anyway.” (Adams, 1990,
p210). On the other hand, God cannot be described as good or loving if the
positive meaning of the lives of His created persons are overwhelmed by and/or
defeated by evil.
She reminds
us of the historic Chalcedonian Definition, where the two natures of Christ come
together into one person and one hypostasis. (Adams, 2000, p164). The divine
nature is eternal and necessary, while the human nature is temporal and
contingent. She appeals to God’s goodness to every person, and that this
goodness is demonstrated by the Incarnation and Christ’s passion on the cross.
Rather than taking the route of “Greater Good” theodicies or the likes of Irenaean
“Soul Making” theodicies, she turns her attention to God’s goodness to every
human person He has created. She contends, “At a minimum, God’s goodness to
human individuals would require that God guarantee each a life that was a great
good to him/her on the whole by balancing off serious evils.” (Adams, 2000,
p31). Thus, for Adams, the defeater for gratuitous evil is God’s “giving [evil]
positive meaning through organic unity with a great enough good within the
context of” a person’s life.
How is
gratuitous evil compatible with a loving, good God? Historic Christianity
answers this question unashamedly,“But he was wounded for our transgressions, he was bruised for
our iniquities: the chastisement of our peace was upon him; and with his
stripes we are healed. (Isa 53:5). Adams contends that God “takes the… approach
of joining us in our defilement.” (Adams, 2000, p98). God indeed through the
Incarnation suffered horrendous evil on our behalf, “For Christ also hath once suffered
for sins, the just for the unjust, that he might bring us to God, being put to
death in the flesh, but quickened by the Spirit (1 Pet 3:18).”
Through this
self-defilement and passion on the cross, God demonstrates His love and
goodness by “being good to all created persons–that is, in seeing to it that
each gets a life that is a great good to him/her on the whole, one in which any
participation in horrors is not merely balanced off but defeated.” (Adams,
2000, p126). Central to Adam’s theodicy is the understanding that God provides
the defeater for gratuitous evil by guaranteeing that every person’s life is a
great good.
Reformed
thinkers would object to her scope of redemption, which “is universalist in
insisting that God be good to each created person.” (Adams, 2000, p157).
Although Adams borders upon Universalism, Reformed thinkers can approach this
thesis with the concept of Common Grace, and that God provides the possibility of such good to every person
(i.e. an atonement that is sufficient for the world, efficient for the elect).
So instead
of directly denying the existence of gratuitous evil (the evidential premise),
Adams’ thesis furnishes a defeater for such horrendous evil using the central
tenets of Christian theology. She continues, “I do claim that because our
eventual post-mortem beatific intimacy with God is an incommensurate good for
human persons, Divine identification with human participation in horrors
confers a positive aspect on such experiences by integrating them into the
participant’s relationship with God.” (Adams, 2000, pp 166-167). She concludes
that from the vantage point of eternity, the “incommensurate” goodness of the
beatific vision viz a viz direct fellowship and intimacy with God would furnish
the ultimate defeater for horrendous evil in this present world.
As
Christians, we can only lament with the Apostle Paul (Rom 11:33) that we do not
know the reason for every specific evil in this present world. “For my thoughts are not your
thoughts, neither are your ways my ways, saith the Lord. For as the heavens are
higher than the earth, so are my ways higher than your ways, and my thoughts
than your thoughts (Isa 55:8-9).”
The story of
Job relates human participation in horrendous evil and suffering, but God does
not give Job His reasons for the evil, and implies that Job is not smart enough
(cognitively, emotionally, and/or spiritually) to understand them. God’s
thoughts are indeed higher than our thoughts, and His secret decrees are
unfathomable. But “these unsearchable paths of God—the thick, dark, heavy
mysteries of Providence — are not absurdities; they are not meaningless. Their
meaning is, however, largely opaque to us now. The morally sufficient reasons
for these evils may be inscrutable, but they are not gratuitous. Nevertheless,
God promises his redeemed children that “in all things God works for the good
of those who love him, who have been called according to his purpose” (Romans
8:28). (Groothuis, Douglas. (2011). Christian
Apologetics: A Comprehensive Case for Biblical Faith. Downers Grove, IL;
Nottingham, England: IVP Academic; Apollos pp 643-644).
No comments:
Post a Comment